Imágenes de páginas
PDF
EPUB

omy, when further advanced, would be able to render an account of many things for which she has not accounted even to this day. Thus, in the passage in the seventh Book of the Republic, he says that the philosopher requires a reason for the proportion of the day to the month, and the month to the year, deeper and more substantial than mere observation can give. Yet Astronomy has not yet shown us any reason why the proportion of the times of the earth's rotation on its axis, the moon's revolution round the earth, and the earth's revolution round the sun, might not have been made by the Creator quite different from what they are. But in thus asking Mathematical Astronomy for reasons which she cannot give, Plato was only doing what a great astronomical discoverer, Kepler, did at a later period. One of the questions which Kepler especially wished to have answered was, why there are five planets, and why at such particular distances from the sun? And it is still more curious that he thought he had found the reason of these things, in the relations of those Five Regular Solids which, as we have seen, Plato was desirous of introducing into the philosophy of the universe. We have Kepler's account of this, his imaginary discovery, in the Mysterium Cosmographicum, published in 1596, as stated in our History, Book v. Chap. iv. Sect. 2.

Kepler regards the law which thus determines the number and magnitude of the planetary orbits by means of the five regular solids as a discovery no less remarkable and certain than the Three Laws which give his name its imperishable place in the history of astronomy.

We are not on this account to think that there is no steady criterion of the difference between imaginary and real discoveries in science. As discovery becomes possible by the liberty of guessing, it becomes real by allowing observation constantly and authoritatively to determine the value of guesses. Kepler added to Plato's boldness of fancy his own patient and candid habit of testing his fancies by a rigorous and laborious comparison with the phenomena; and thus his discoveries led to those of Newton.

CHAPTER I.

EARLIEST STAGES OF ASTRONOMY.

The Globular Form of the Earth.

THERE HERE are parts of Plato's writings which have been adduced as bearing upon the subsequent progress of science; and especially upon the globular form of the earth, and the other views which led to the discovery of America. In the Timaus we read of a great continent lying in the Ocean west of the Pillars of Hercules, which Plato calls Atlantis. He makes the personage in his Dialogue who speaks of this put it forward as an Egyptian tradition. M. H. Martin, who has discussed what has been written respecting the Atlantis of Plato, and has given therein a dissertation rich in erudition and of the most lively interest, conceives that Plato's notions on this subject arose from his combining his conviction of the spherical form of the earth, with interpretations of Homer, and perhaps with traditions which were current in Egypt (Etudes sur le Timée, Note xiii. § ix.). He does not consider that the belief in Plato's Atlantis had any share in the discoveries of Columbus.

It may perhaps surprise modern readers who have a difficulty in getting rid of the persuasion that there is a natural direction upwards and a natural direction downwards, to learn that both Plato and Aristotle, and of course other philosophers also, had completely overcome this difficulty. They were quite ready to allow and to conceive that down meant nothing but towards some centre, and up, the opposite direction. (Aristotle has, besides, an ingenious notion that while heavy bodies, as earth and water, tend to the centre, and light bodies, as fire, tend from the centre, the fifth element, of which the heavenly bodies. are composed, tends to move round the centre.)

Plato explains this in the most decided manner in the Timæus (62, c). "It is quite erroneous to suppose that there are two opposite regions in the universe, one above and the other below; and that heavy things naturally tend to the latter place. The heavens are spherical, and every thing tends to the centre; and thus above and below have no real meaning. If there be a solid globe in the middle,

and if a person walk round it, he will become the antipodes to himself, and the direction which is up at one time will be down at another."

The notion of antipodes, the inhabitants of the part of the globe of the earth opposite to ourselves, was very familiar. Thus in Cicero's Academic Questions (ii. 39) one of the speakers says, "Etiam dicitis esse e regione nobis, e contraria parte terræ, qui adversis vestigiis stant contra nostra vestigia, quos Antipodas vocatis." See also Tusc. Disp. i. 28 and v. 24.

The Heliocentric System among the Ancients.

As the more clear-sighted of the ancients had overcome the natural prejudice of believing that there is an absolute up and down, so had they also overcome the natural prejudice of believing that the earth is at rest. Cicerò says (Acad. Quest. ii. 39), "Hicetas of Syracuse, as Theophrastus tells us, thinks that the heavens, the sun, the moon, the stars do not move; and that nothing does move but the earth. The earth revolves about her axis with immense velocity; and thus the same effect is produced as if the earth were at rest and the heavens moved; and this, he says, Plato teaches in the Timæus, though somewhat obscurely." Of course the assertion that the moon and planets do not move, was meant of the diurnal motion only. The passage referred to in the Timæus seems to be this (40, c)—" As to the Earth, which is our nurse, and which clings to the axis which stretches through the universe, God made her the producer and preserver of day and night." The word eiλλouévny, which I have translated clings to, some translate revolves; and an extensive controversy has prevailed, both in ancient and modern times (beginning with Aristotle), whether Plato did or did not believe in the rotation of the earth on her axis. (See M. Cousin's Note on the Timæus, and M. Henri Martin's Dissertation, Note xxxvii., in his Etudes sur le Timée.) The result of this discussion seems to be that, in the Timaeus, the Earth is supposed to be at rest. It is however related by Plutarch (Platonic Questions, viii. 1). that Plato in his old age repented of having given to the Earth the place in the centre of the universe which did not belong to it.

In describing the Prelude to the Epoch of Copernicus (Book v. Chap. i.), I have spoken of Philolaus, one of the followers of Pythagoras, who lived at the time of Socrates, as having held the doctrine that the earth revolves about the sun. This has been a current opin

ion;-so current, indeed, that the Abbé Bouillaud, or Bullialdus, as we more commonly call him, gave the title of Philolaus to the defence of Copernicus which he published in 1639; and Chiaramonti, an Aristotelian, published his answer under the title of Antiphilolaus. In 1645 Bullialdus published his Astronomia Philolaica, which was another exposition of the heliocentric doctrine.

Yet notwithstanding this general belief, it appears to be tolerably certain that Philolaus did not hold the doctrine of the earth's motion round the sun. (M. H. Martin, Etudes sur le Timée, 1841, Note xxxvii. Sect. i.; and Boeckh, De vera Indole Astronomia Philolaica, 1810.) In the system of Philolaus, the earth revolved about the central fire; but this central fire was not the sun. The Sun, along with the moon and planets, revolved in circles external to the earth. The Earth had the Antichthon or Counter-Earth between it and the centre; and revolving round this centre in one day, the Antichthon, being always between it and the centre, was, during a portion of the revolution, interposed between the Earth and the Sun, and thus made night; while the Sun, by his proper motion, produced the changes of the year.

When men were willing to suppose the earth to be in motion, in order to account for the recurrence of day and night, it is curious that they did not see that the revolution of a spherical earth about an axis passing through its centre was a scheme both simple and quite satisfactory. Yet the illumination of a globular earth by a distant sun, and the circumstances and phenomena thence resulting, appear to have been conceived in a very confused manner by many persons. Thus Tacitus (Agric. xii.), after stating that he has heard that in the northern part of the island of Britain, the night disappears in the height of summer, says, as his account of this phenomenon, that "the extreme parts of the earth are low and level, and do not throw their shadow upwards; so that the shade of night falls below the sky and the stars." But, as a little consideration will show, it is the globular form of the earth, and not the level character of the country, which produces this effect.

It is not in any degree probable that Pythagoras taught that the Earth revolves round the Sun, or that it rotates on its own axis. Nor did Plato hold either of these motions of the Earth. They got so far as to believe in the Spherical Form of the Earth; and this was apparently such an effort that the human mind made a pause before going any further. "It required," says M. H. Martin, "a great struggle for

men to free themselves from the prejudices of the senses, and to interpret their testimony in such a manner as to conceive the sphericity of the earth. It is natural that they should have stopped at this point, before putting the earth in motion in space."

Some of the expressions which have been understood as describing a system in which the Sun is the centre of motion, do really imply merely the Sun is the middle term of the series of heavenly bodies which revolve round the earth: the series being Moon, Mercury, Venus, Sun, Mars, Jupiter, Saturn. This is the case, for instance, in a passage of Cicero's Vision of Scipio, which has been supposed to imply (as I have stated in the History), that Mercury and Venus revolve about the Sun.

But though the doctrine of the diurnal rotation and annual revolution of the earth is not the doctrine of Pythagoras, or of Philolaus, or of Plato, it was nevertheless held by some of the philosophers of antiquity. The testimony of Archimedes that this doctrine was held by his contemporary Aristarchus of Samos, is unquestionable; and there is no reason to doubt Plutarch's assertion that Seleucus further enforced it.

It is curious that Copernicus appears not to have known any thing of the opinions of Aristarchus and Seleucus, which were really anticipations of his doctrine; and to have derived his notion from passages which, as I have been showing, contain no such doctrine. He says, in his Dedication to Pope Paul III., "I found in Cicero that Nicetas [or Hicetas] held that the earth was in motion: and in Plutarch I found that some others had been of that opinion; and his words I will transcribe, that any one may read them: Philosophers in general hold that the earth is at rest. But Philolaus the Pythagorean teaches that it moves round the central fire in an oblique circle, in the same direction as the Sun and the Moon. Heraclides of Pontus and Ecphantus the Pythagorean give the earth a motion, but not a motion of translation; they make it revolve like a wheel about its own centre from west to east.' This last opinion was a correct assertion of the diurnal motion.

[ocr errors]

The Eclipse of Thales.

"THE Eclipse of Thales" is so remarkable a point in the history of astronomy, and has been the subject of so much discussion among astronomers, that it ought to be more especially noticed. The original

« AnteriorContinuar »